Nudge, embarrassment, and restriction-replies to Voigt, Tieffenbach, and Saghai.

نویسنده

  • Nir Eyal
چکیده

It is a privilege that some of the most promising contributors to public health ethics took the time to think and comment on my op-ed. Kristin Voigt’s (1), Emma Tieffenbach’s (2), and Yashar Saghai’s (3) ingenious comments have taught me a lot about nudging, embarrassment, and restriction. Let me address their main points one by one. Kristin Voigt makes two points. One is that nudging by shaming can be either paternalistic or non-paternalistic and that, like any intervention, it is easier to justify when it is nonpaternalistic. Indeed, whereas nudges were originally conceived as “libertarian paternalistic” and used behavioral psychology to promote paternalistic goals only (4,5), nudges (6) and behavior psychology in general (7,8) can promote non-paternalistic goals as well. What is less obvious is that a paternalistic intervention is always harder to justify than a similar non-paternalistic one. Sarah Conly writes, “If it is permissible, even obligatory, to stop me when I do something that seriously interferes with someone else’s chances of achieving the life he wants, I think it is equally permissible, and perhaps obligatory, to save me from myself ” (7). In fact, is not it easier to justify forcing a child to eat her broccoli for her own sake than for her sister’s sake—say, when her young sister looks up to her example? And isn’t forcing a Jehovah’s Witness to accept blood transfusion against his religious edicts easier to justify when the goal is paternalistic, to save his life—than when the goal is to save the lives of his starving related dependents? Voigt’s other comment is that there are two quite different routes through which zoning laws can shame or stigmatize smokers into quitting: directly, by temporarily shunning them from a certain geographical zone, and indirectly, by denormalizing smoking and provoking many instances of grass root social disapproval of smoking and of smokers. She says correctly that I was focusing on the first route and warns that the second, more dangerous route is a real potential. In Voigt’s second route, the intention to induce shame and stigma will typically be more transparent. That may weaken its impact on shame and stigma: “an expression of contempt may induce shame if seen as spontaneous but cause anger if seen as intended to induce shame” (8). Even if denormalizing turns out to be efficacious, it would be responsible both for making smokers’ social lives harder in one respect and for a lot of quitting and a lot of smoking-prevention. So long as any resulting social penalties for smokers remain by and large moderate, denormalizing smoking would usually remain justified on balance. In every *Correspondence to: Nir Eyal, Email: [email protected] Copyright: © 2015 by Kerman University of Medical Sciences Citation: Eyal N. Nudge, embarrassment, and restriction—replies to Voigt, Tieffenbach, and Saghai. Int J Health Policy Manag 2015; 4: 53-54. doi: 10.15171/ijhpm.2015.01 Received: 27 November 2014, Accepted: 4 December 2014, ePublished: 5 December 2014 society, some behaviors are considered abnormal. Saving scores of lives is almost always worth the social risks and harms from limited added stigma, lamentable as the latter may be otherwise. Emma Tieffenbach points out that shame can be subjectively painful (it can be “felt as dread”) and lead to destructive reactions like extreme anger. She concludes that shaming is not nudging: the latter is supposed to be costless. Our preference for averting specific embarrassments of the form in which I am interested is adaptive (9). Once frustrated, that preference quickly wanes in strength, such that over our lifetimes, the overall hedonic loss from its frustration—the subjective cost—remains small. As an illustration, consider a person who is lonely because she moved to a new city but is too embarrassed to strike conversation with strangers. If somehow she found herself in conversation, the experience could be positive. Strong aversion to initiating conversations will have preceded the event. But if the embarrassment she dreaded materializes, it would not translate into a lasting strong unpleasant sensation—dreaded as it may have been. Such a person’s form of embarrassment sharply contrasts with the lasting, deep shame and humiliation that can haunt victims of torture decades after physical pain is past (10). I believe that the embarrassment from not being permitted to smoke on the premises is a form of embarrassment (not deep shame) that worries us and may make smokingavoidance significantly likelier but that when it materializes, it rarely feels lastingly dreadful. Sunstein recently emphasized that what scares us and we are willing to pay plenty to avoid is not necessarily a very bad prospect (11). My proposal is to focus on a form of embarrassment that, thanks to our adaptive preferences, is not a very bad prospect. Moreover, consider again the person who dreads conversation with strangers. If she were interviewed on whether a third party is promoting his own good by choosing loneliness over starting a conversation, she may well judge that lasting loneliness is worse than fleeting embarrassment. If asked to list the components of the good life, she is likelier to include on the list having friends than to include avoiding small embarrassments like starting a conversation. In a reflective moment, she may recognize that the dreaded embarrassment in fact is about a trifle; the sort of realization that can drive cognitive-behavioral therapy. Her strong (ex ante) preference to avoid embarrassment lacks her own endorsement (12). I believe that the same could be said about the embarrassment of, e.g. returning for many refills of one’s soda cup, the example to which Tieffenbach reacts. These embarrassments are far less morally concerning than the obesity epidemic that they may help combat. It is true that sometimes, people systematically underestimate in advance the toll of stigma and shame on them. According to some reports (13), many Iranian kidney sellers experience far more stigma than anyone could have predicted. Dostoyevsky’s Raskolnikov winds up feeling more shameful about his

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

منابع مشابه

On the Cost of Shame; Comment on “Nudging by Shaming, Shaming by Nudging”

In his editorial, Nir Eyal argues that a nudge can exploit our propensity to feel shame in order to steer us toward certain choices. We object that shame is a cost and therefore cannot figure in the apparatus of a nudge.

متن کامل

On the cost of shame : Comment on "Nudging by shaming, shaming by nudging".

In his editorial, Nir Eyal argues that a nudge can exploit our propensity to feel shame in order to steer us toward certain choices. We object that shame is a cost and therefore cannot figure in the apparatus of a nudge.

متن کامل

Salvaging the concept of nudge.

In recent years, 'nudge' theory has gained increasing attention for the design of population-wide health interventions. The concept of nudge puts a label on efficacious influences that preserve freedom of choice without engaging the influencees' deliberative capacities. Given disagreements over what it takes genuinely to preserve freedom of choice, the question is whether health influences rely...

متن کامل

Radically Questioning the Principle of the Least Restrictive Alternative: A Reply to Nir Eyal; Comment on “Nudging by Shaming, Shaming by Nudging”

In his insightful editorial, Nir Eyal explores the connections between nudging and shaming. One upshot of his argument is that we should question the principle of the least restrictive alternative in public health and health policy. In this commentary, I maintain that Eyal’s argument undermines only a rather implausible version of the principle of the least restrictive alternative and I sketch ...

متن کامل

ذخیره در منابع من


  با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

عنوان ژورنال:
  • International journal of health policy and management

دوره 4 1  شماره 

صفحات  -

تاریخ انتشار 2015